1
ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE REIMAGINE THE RULES
570 LEXINGTON AVE, 5TH FLOOR, NEW YORK, NY 10022 | 212.444.9130 | @ROOSEVELTINST | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
Addressing Climate Change Through Price
and Non-Price Interventions
Roosevelt Institute Working Paper
Joseph E. Stiglitz
December 2019
I am deeply indebted to Linus Mattauch, Cameron Hepburn, and Naman Garg, and two very helpful anonymous referees
for their detailed and helpful comments. I am also indebted to Nick Stern for long conversations about the subjects covered
here, and the members of the High-Level Commission on Carbon Prices for their insights and debates over the issues
discussed here. I am also indebted to Andrea Gurwitt for her editorial assistance. Financial support was provided by INET.
The views expressed herein are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of the Roosevelt Institute.
2
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
ABSTRACT
Recognizing the importance of the second-best nature of economies, the Stern-Stiglitz report on
carbon pricing departed from the recommendation of a single carbon price for all uses at all places
and times. This paper provides some of the analytics behind these recommendations. First, I analyze
the circumstances in which distributional concerns make desirable a tax or regulation inducing
significant reductions in carbon usage in a carbon-intensive sector for which consumers are
disproportionately rich. Such policies allow lower carbon prices elsewhere without exceeding carbon
emission targets. The cost of the resulting production inefficiency may, under the identified
circumstances, be less than the distributional benefits. The paper considers the circumstances in
which such differential policies may be best implemented through regulation vs. differential pricing,
as well as differential effects on political economy and norm setting. Second, I consider the effect of
carbon price trajectories on induced innovation, providing general conditions under which the
optimal carbon path should, at least eventually, be falling over time. Finally, I revisit the price-versus-
quantity debate and highlight important aspects of the dynamic nature of the problem.
3
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
Introduction
Economists have had a long predilection for price interventions to correct market failures such as
those arising from the presence of externalities. The reason is simple: market efficiency requires
equating private and social returns, the presence of an externality means that there is a gap
between the two, and a price intervention can close the gap, restoring efficiency. In the context of
climate change, the prescription is to price carbon, and since what matters is the atmospheric
concentration of greenhouse gases, and since the rate of decay of, say, carbon dioxide is so slow,
the price of carbon should be (approximately) the same for all uses, at all places, and at all dates.
(IPCC 2013; Stiglitz, 2013; Millar et al., 2016; Dietz and Venmans, 2017; van der Ploeg, 2018).
1
If only things were so simple. There are several fundamental departures from this simplistic world,
all speaking to the point that we are always in a second- or third-best world, and in such a world,
naively moving the economy seemingly closer to first best may entail a lowering of social welfare.
2
The Stern-Stiglitz High-Level Commission on Carbon Prices (2017), while recognizing that “A well-
designed carbon price is an indispensable part of a strategy for reducing emissions in an efficient
way,” departed from the “single price of carbon in all place, dates, and uses,” calling for “explicit
price trajectories.” The Commission, in formulating optimal strategies for meeting the Paris and
Copenhagen goals, also did not rely exclusively on carbon pricing, suggesting that such pricing
“may need to be complemented by other well-designed policies tackling various market and
government failures, as well as other imperfections.” It observed that, “Adopting other cost-
effective policies can mean that a given emission reduction may be induced with lower carbon
prices than if those policies were absent.” All of these considerations represent marked departures
from the standard first-best model alluded to in the first paragraph of this paper. While these ideas
received the support of all the members of the Commission, the Commission in its report did not
provide analytic justifications for these departures from the conventional wisdom. Implicitly, the
report seems to suggest different shadow prices of carbon across time, over space, and with
1
The economic argument for a single price is straightforward: Climate change is a result of the increase in
the atmospheric concentrations of carbon dioxide and other greenhouse gases. Assume, for instance, that
there were a precise carbon budgetno climate change so long as carbon concentration was below a
critical threshold, and unacceptable change over that level. Because of the long duration that any CO2
molecule entering the atmosphere remains there, we don’t care when the molecules enter the atmosphere.
There is thus a shadow price associated with molecules entering the atmosphereand this is the carbon
price, the same at all places and times. Other greenhouse gases obviously also play a role in climate change,
and because they are (relatively) short- lived, it is not quite accurate to focus only on the long run.
2
See Lipsey and Lancaster (1956) for a general theory of second best.
4
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
different uses, and that these shadow prices would themselves be contingent on information as it
was revealed.
3
The intent of this paper is not to provide a general alternative analytic framework, but through a
series of simple, partial equilibrium models, to enhance our intuition for the Stern-Stiglitz
recommendations, and to provide a better sense of the circumstances under which a deviation
from the “single price” might be desirable, and the form that such deviations might best take. We
focus in particular on distribution and induced innovation, and the appropriate responses to
uncertainties about developments in technology and our knowledge of climate change, including
its economic and social impacts.
We draw on the extensive public finance literature that has addressed analogous questions.
Unfortunately, many of the complicated and subtle insights from that literature have not been fully
brought into discussions related to climate change. While earlier literature on corrective taxation in
a second-best world with optimal commodity taxation (Sandmo, 1975)
4
where there were no pure
profits and no restrictions on commodity taxessuggested that a standard Pigouvian analysis in
which simple taxes can address externalities would apply, more recent work has questioned these
results. One essential question relates to the circumstances in which the Diamond-Mirrlees
efficiency conditions apply (Diamond and Mirrlees, 1971). When it does, then a Pigouvian corrective
tax ensures production efficiency, and optimal consumption (including optimal wage) taxes can be
used to raise the requisite revenue in a way that maximizes social welfare (or alternatively, do so in
a way that is Pareto efficient.
5
) Unfortunately, it turns out that the conditions under which the
Diamond-Mirrlees efficiency hold are very restrictive, requiring, for instance, a wide range of rent,
profits, and differential product and wage taxes (Dasgupta and Stiglitz, 1971, 1972). And even more
so when individuals differ in their abilities and relative wages are endogenous and offsetting
differential wage taxes cannot be levied or when they differ in their ownership of other assets the
returns to which could not be fully differentially taxed (Stiglitz, 1998a, 2018b). Thus, with restrictive
taxation, a tax on carbon could lead to a change in the distribution of income or well-being, either
3
Even a single carbon price “at all places, at all dates, and in all uses” will be state contingent, i.e. will change
with changes in information about technology and damage, so that in practice, the carbon price will change
over time.
4
Baumol and Oates (1971) argued for the desirability of using Pigouvian taxation even when there was
uncertainty about the appropriate level of emission reductions.
5
For a general analysis extending the standard theory of optimal taxation to the theory of Pareto efficient
taxation, see Stiglitz (1987).
5
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
because of direct price effects or because of indirect general equilibrium effects on relative wages
and prices; and the government may not have at its disposal instruments to undo these distributive
effects. In these cases, Pigouvian corrective taxation does not suffice to “undo” the externality in
ways which maximize societal welfare. In short, in the second-best world in which we live, there is
no presumption that a carbon tax alone can suffice to address optimally the problem of climate
change. To the contrary, there is a presumption that additional interventions can increase societal
welfare.
6
Earlier results showing that when information is imperfect and/or asymmetric and risk markets
incompletethat is alwaysmarkets are not (constrained) Pareto efficient imply, of course, that
climate change is never the only “market failure.”
7
These microeconomic externalities imply there
are likely to be significant macroeconomic externalities (Jeane and Korinek, 2010) that government
policy will need to take into account. While these, too, may sometimes be effectively addressed
through price interventions, the relevant price interventions will differ from sector to sector,
6
The mathematics establishing these results is straightforward. The usual Lagrangean associated with
maximizing social welfare (and Pareto optimality, where the well-being of one group is maximized subject to
the levels attained by other groups) incorporates the limitations on government redistribution, e.g. by
embedding self- selection constraints and limiting the set of taxes/interventions. It turns out that with specific
utility functions, where, for instance, leisure is separable from goods and where the effects of climate change
are separable from goods and leisure, and if the government is allowed to impose unrestricted non-linear
income and commodity taxes, then the standard efficiency results can be restored (Kaplow, 1996, 2006,
building on Atkinson and Stiglitz, 1976). But even with strong separability conditions, if the government were
restricted in its income tax, say to a linear income tax, then public policy once again has to take into account
distributive effects (Stiglitz, 2009).
The work of Goulder, Hafstead, and William (2016) can perhaps best be looked at in this way. They provide a
special model in which they show the desirability of using a clean energy standard over simply using a price:
“On the other hand, lower electricity prices have a virtue associated with tax interactions. Because it gives
rise to a less pronounced increase in electricity prices, the [clean energy standard (CES)] leads to smaller
distortions caused by the tax system. Our models indicate that this offsetting benefit makes the CES nearly as
cost-effective asand in some cases more cost-effective thanthe equivalent emissions price policy” (p.188).
Our analysis is very much in their spirit, though they do not point out clearly what departure from the
Diamond-Mirrlees model justifies a departure from using a single price intervention. In the analysis below, as
we’ll see, the departure relates to costly redistributions, which seem not to play the central role in their
model.
While this paper focuses on costly redistributions, other restrictions in the set of admissible taxes also give
rise to the desirability of going beyond just a carbon tax, for instance, restrictions on the imposition of
different tax rates on different products and restrictions on the imposition of taxes on rents. When, for
instance, there are rents, a higher carbon tax may be viewed as an indirect way of taxing rents in some
sectors.
The difference between Ramsey’s analysis of commodity taxationwhere taxes were related to the elasticity
of supply as well as demandand that of Diamond and Mirrleeswhere only demand is relevantarises from
the absence of rents in the latter model or the complete taxation away of those rents. See Dasgupta and
Stiglitz (1971).
Cross-country redistributive issues are more complex, and more difficult to resolve, than those addressed
here, and this provides an even more compelling case for a deviation from a global single carbon price. See
Stiglitz (2017).
7
See Greenwald and Stiglitz (1986) and Geanakoplos and Polemarcharkis (1986). The term “constrained
Pareto optimality” simply refers to the fact that, even taking into account the costs of obtaining information
and creating markets, the equilibrium is not Pareto efficient.
6
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
depending on the nature of these macroeconomic externalities and spillovers. Moreover, private
decisions are also affected by publicly provided infrastructure.
While prices may help guide these decisions, inevitably market imperfections, such as those
associated with geography, loom large, and limit the guidance that can be provided by carbon
prices alone. And government itself seldom relies on pricing alone (or even shadow prices) in
making its resource allocations.
8
It is this and similar insights, all of which can be framed as second or third best deviations from the
“standard model,” that informed our thinking. If the standard economists’ arguments were correct,
and if (as is conventionally assumed) citizens are rational, it would appear that there should be
strong support for a carbon tax, accompanied perhaps by some measures to ensure that those
who might lose from a carbon tax are made whole. But so far, few countries have enacted
significant carbon taxes, let alone relied on them to curb the use of fossil fuels, and there remains
significant opposition from various quarters. In one sense, this paper is an enquiry into whether
there might exist a rationale for such opposition, and if so, are there reforms in the design of the
carbon tax (perhaps along the lines suggested by the Stern-Stiglitz Report) that might result in a
broader consensus behind it.
Beyond the introduction and the conclusion, this paper is divided into four sections. In the first, I lay
out some of the important, but not always transparent, assumptions that shape public policy. In the
second, I focus more narrowly on designing carbon policy when distributional considerations are
important, and there are not first best, or often even second best, mechanisms for undoing the
distributive consequences of carbon pricing. In the third, I focus on the interactions between pricing
trajectories and innovation, addressing the question of whether it might be desirable to begin with a
high carbon price which would subsequently be reduced. In the fourth section, I have a few remarks
about an old puzzlethe merits of using prices vs. quantitiesin the context of climate change.
The core assumptions
This paper is, in many ways, an exploration of optimal policy in contexts in which there are multiple
market failures and public policy constraints, not just a single market failure- excessive emissions of
8
Stiglitz (2018b) explains why, even if it were guided by shadow prices, government would not necessarily want
to use the same shadow prices for all projects, in all periods, and in all locations, and would not want to use the
same prices used by markets.
7
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
carbon that could be corrected by a single intervention, imposing a carbon price.
9
It may be useful,
in this introductory section, to lay out the range of deviations from the standard first best model
and the constraints on government that we will explore in subsequent sections.
The standard simple model of optimal environmental intervention has a well-defined damage
function, a well-defined damage abatement (emissions reduction) function, a representative
consumer, and costless adjustment, and the only market failure is the absence of a carbon price. In
this context, it is obvious that direct regulation (specifying the quantity of allowable emissions) and
price regulation (specifying a fine for emissions) are equivalent. Much of the “folk” policy literature
assumes that the government may not know precisely the abatement function or even the damage
function at the time the policy is imposed. If, of course, the government knows precisely the
marginal damage cost, then imposing a fine equal to the marginal damage cost achieves the first
best outcome. But if, as in Weitzman (1974), the damage function is itself unknown
10
, then ex ante,
we don’t know what the optimal fine (price) should be. Weitzman’s early analysis made it clear, at
least as a matter of principle, that the economists’ presumption in favor of the use of price
interventions was more limited than had previously been thought.
11
This paper explores a set of complementary reasons for policy to go beyond a carbon tax in
support of the conclusions of the Stern-Stiglitz Commission, some of which go beyond the
considerations that have preoccupied optimal tax-and-expenditure theory.
2.1 Welfare criteria. Much of this paper focuses on the observation that carbon taxes have distributive
implications. In particular, it may be (if carbon consumption increases less than in proportion to
income), and be perceived to be, regressive.
12
Levinson (2018) argues that for the US, the rich
consume more energy but not proportionately so, so that a carbon tax is regressive. More broadly, it
9
As we have noted in the next section, we focus on limitations on the ability to redistribute income, limitations
which, in turn, may be explicable in terms of imperfections of information. See Mirrlees (1971) and Stiglitz
(1987b). In section 4, we focus on inherent market failures in the innovation process.
10
Or if there is uncertainty about the abatement function and the damage function is upward-sloping.
11
In a sense, Weitzman’s work could be set in the context of the extensive work on optimal policy, and
especially optimal taxation, with asymmetries of information between the government and agents, where it
had been shown that it was optimal to have non-linear interventions, i.e. neither relying on price or quantity
interventions, if such non-linear interventions are implementable. The formal similarities between the various
screening/signaling/optimal tax models are, by now, well-recognized. See, e.g. Mirrlees (1971, 1975) and
Atkinson and Stiglitz (1976, 1980).
12
Even if a carbon tax is progressive, it may be less progressive than other tax instruments, so that shifting
towards a carbon tax can reduce the progressivity of the tax system. Of course, as we discuss below, there
are other changes to policy that can offset these effects, but whether these offsetting measures will be
undertaken and sustained is a different matter, which we also discuss below.
8
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
can have large adverse distributive consequences which cannot easily be undone.
13
This was
illustrated by the refrain of France’s yellow vest protestors in response to the proposal for an increase
in gasoline taxes, viewed as part of the broader agenda of creating a carbon price in France. “The
government talks about the end of the world. We are worried about the end of the month.”
14
(Of
course, it didn’t help that the government had earlier lowered taxes on the wealthiest French citizens.)
At least for some important aspects of energy consumptionin the home and for public
transportationprices charged the poor do not have to increase in tandem with the price of
carbon. There can be non-linear electricity tariffs that undo the distributive effects of the carbon tax
for the poor, and public transportation, especially for the poor, can be subsidized. More generally,
there are combinations of interventions that may reduce carbon consumption and still be
progressive.
In addition to the standard vertical inequities (between the rich and the poor), we also consider
horizontal inequities (impacts of a tax on individuals, say, with the same income, who differ in their
consumption preferences). Such differences provide a critique of proposals to rebate the carbon
tax
15
. While on average, a uniform lump sum payment may more than compensate low income
individuals for increased energy coststhe evidence, as we have already noted, is that carbon
consumption on average increases with incomethere are sub-groups for whom that may not be
true. A more distributively sensitive but less efficient policya carbon tax exempting fuel (which
already has a high implicit carbon tax)might increase social welfare and might not have run into
such opposition.
16
Governments are often adverse to policies that introduce large differences among individuals who
previously seemed similarly situated, even if the differences are related to the extent to which they
13
By adverse distribution effects, we simply mean redistributions that lower the level of social welfare under an
inequality averse social welfare function, e.g. distributive effects against the poor.
14
Interestingly, transportation may be the one sector in which energy/carbon usage increases more than in
proportion to income, partly because many poor do not own cars. See Grainger and Kolstad (2010) for the
US. More generally, see Flues and Thomas (2015) and Sterner (2012). The yellow-vests protests seems to
have reflected concerns of a particular subgroup that face high fuel costs. Because of where low income
housing is located in relation to work opportunities, the working poor often have to travel long distances.
15
Such a proposal received the support of a broad coalition of American economists in a letter published in the
Wall Street Journal on January 19, 2019. Other critiques are based on the arguments provided in later
sections of this paper, as well as the inefficiencies of providing lump sum redistributions and subsequently
having to impose distortionary taxes to raise revenues, including those required for green infrastructure. The
major argument put forward for such proposals is based on political economy, the ability to garner sufficient
political support for a carbon tax. We comment on these political economy arguments below.
16
In the discussion below, we will explain why the government may not able to offset these distributional
impacts.
9
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
generate negative societal externalities
17
. This is especially true if the government is sensitive to
loss aversion
18
the fact that those who lose from the high carbon tax lose more, or perceive those
losses more intensely, than those who gain from the restructured tax structure (e.g. from lower
taxes on labor and capital).
The significance of these distribution effects will depend, of course, on the nature of the economy
and the set of instruments available to government. The costs of undoing any adverse distributive
consequences is affected also by the diversity of the population. Distributive consequences will be
larger in a society in which there are greater disparities in income and greater societal
heterogeneity. The former is a standard argument in the theory of optimal taxation, but the latter has
not been given sufficient attention, partly because much of the literature, beginning with Mirrlees
(1971), focused on vertical inequalities in models where all individuals of a given income were
identical. An implication is that it might be desirable to have more reliance on regulations and
restraints in an economy with a high level of inequality and diversity, like the US, than in a society
with greater equality and less diversity.
Still a third concern is risk. Individuals are risk averse, and cannot obtain insurance against many of
the risks that they faceincluding the uncertainties posed by policy itself. In a world in which
individuals may not be sure about the full distributive consequences of a carbon tax, risk aversion
will mean that a carbon tax lowers their ex ante expected utility. Risk averse individuals may
believe that a carbon tax (even when accompanied by a lump-sum redistribution) might make them
worse off, simply because they are uncertain about the general equilibrium effects.
19
17
And even if similar changes in well-being could have resulted from changes in market prices. The implication
for the cost of energy of the Stern-Stiglitz recommended price of carbon is far smaller than variations in the
prices of energy that have often occurred over the past 40 years. (See, for instance, Stiglitz 2018c).
18
See, e.g. Tversky and Kahneman 1991. As we note below, individuals may not be fully aware of their levels
of carbon consumption, and therefore of the impact of say a carbon tax. Loss aversion is defined relative to
their current level of utility.
Similar results may hold in a standard utilitarian analysis with concave utility functions, where individuals differ in
their preferences, even when the carbon tax is uniformly fully rebated. For non-negligible taxes, the increase
in utility of the gainers (low carbon consumers) may be less than the loss in utility of the losers (high carbon
consumers). This is even more so, as we note below, in a standard ex ante utilitarian analysis where
individuals are uncertain about the consequences of the carbon tax, even if they have rational expectations
concerning average impacts.
19
These individuals will, of course, oppose the tax, unless there is some credible way to compensate them.
There is clearly a close relationship between these risk effects and the horizontal inequities discussed in the
previous paragraphs, where particular individuals may believe that a carbon tax accompanied by a uniform
lump sum distribution may make them worse off also because they believe that their (general equilibrium)
carbon consumption might be greater than the average per capita and/or they believe that their costs of
adjustment are significant. Imperfections in competition may also result in adverse distribution effects, with
goods prices going up more than proportionately to costs of production. The imposition of a carbon tax may
provide an opportunity for those with market power to take advantage of them. There is ample evidence that
firms often increase prices following an increase in taxes in ways that are markedly different from what one
10
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
A fourth concern (taken up briefly in section 5) combines risk and the absence of a full set of
insurance markets and fully state contingent policies and a particular aspect of distribution
intergenerational equity. Alternative policies have implications for intergenerational distribution,
including that of risk bearing, the consequences of which are not fully offset by intergenerational
transfers.
20
There is a final set of modifications to the simplistic welfare framework that we take into account:
adjustment is costly, both financially and psychically, and it is the latter that raises the most
problematic issues.
Moreover, advances in behavioral economics have detailed the many ways in which individuals
differ from the homo oeconemus of standard theory, both in limited cognitive capacities and in the
endogeneity of preferences, which to a large extent are culturally determined.
21
Policies predicated
on analyses of rational agents with fixed preferences often go astray, simply because the
underlying predicate that agents are rational with fixed preferences is so off the mark. Public
policies aimed at increasing savings making use of insights from behavioral economics seem far
more efficacious than those based on the conventional model of individuals maximizing the
standard intertemporal utility function. And this may be particularly important when it comes to the
establishment of norms when individually rational behavior is so out of tune with societal well-
being.
would have expected in a fully competitive equilibrium. Uncertainty about the degree of market power (and
there is again ample evidence of such uncertainty, especially in the midst of on-going increases in market
power) will lead to uncertainty about the effects of a carbon tax.
20
Limitations in such intergenerational transfers is one of the reasons that the rate of discount to be used in
social cost benefit analysis may differ from the pure rate of discounting of future generations (plus an
adjustment for the decline in marginal utility as a result of technological change). See, e.g. Stiglitz 1982.
(Other reasons have to do with other market imperfections, e.g. limitations in the ability to costlessly transfer
money from the private sector to the public. See Stiglitz 2018b.)
21
This has been called by Hoff and Stiglitz (2016) the second strand of behavioral economics. The original
work in behavioral economics, based on insights from psychology, focused on cognitive limitations,
analyzing how these often led to decisions that seemed inconsistent with individuals’ deep preferences. This
second strand, by contrast, draws on insights from social psychology and sociology, and is centered on the
determination of these deep preferences and societal norms. There is a growing literature on endogenous
preferences and how preferences and norms are shaped. See, e.g., Bowles (1998, 2016).
An often cited example is Israeli day care centers: charging parents for picking up their children late from a
daycare center actually exacerbated the problem of late pickups. Previously, it had been a “norm” to pick up
a child on time, and parents struggled to conform to the norm. But a charge made a late pickup into an
ordinary commodity, with parents evaluating the costs and benefits (Gneezy and Rustichini, 2000). For a
more recent survey, see Gneezy et al 2011
Endogeneity of preferences poses difficult problems in welfare economics (see, e.g. Gintis, 1974), but, as we
shall see, can play an important role in addressing climate change. In the context of climate change, see also
Mattauch and Hepburn, 2016.
11
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
One important insight of behavioral economics already noted is that individuals are “loss averse.”
This means that the societal consequences of a policy that symmetrically imposed losses on some
individuals and gains to others would lower social welfare: the losses of the losers would be more
salient than the gains of the winners. Greater salience can easily translate into greater political
activism.
22
The introduction of behavioral economics into our analysis, though, presents a challenge which this
paper cannot resolve: We know less about the determinants either of preferences and norms or of
deviations from full rationality than we would like. While even if we can’t provide adequate answer
to the relative merits of prices and regulations in changing preferences and norms, it is important to
raise the issue: in the end, this question may be of first order importance.
2.2 Innovation. A standard result in modern welfare economics is that market economies are
essentially never efficient when it comes to the pace and direction of innovation. (Stiglitz and
Greenwald, 2014). Knowledge is a quasi-public good, and there are significant spillovers from
innovation. Government policies can affect the direction of innovation, and not just through its role
in providing direct support, especially for basic research. It can, for instance, do so through prices
and regulations. A long-established theory of induced innovation provides an intellectual framework
guiding us in understanding how that happens and the merits of alternative policies.
These issues interact, of course, with those discussed earlier: innovation can have significant
distributive effects, and changes in norms, preferences, and capabilities can both help shape the
direction of innovation and affect the social consequences.
2.3 Political economy. Economists often refer vaguely to “political constraints”: a particular policy
(such as a carbon tax) would be first best, but because of ill-defined political constraints, there is a
need for a second best policy. My experience in politics has left me with an uncertain feeling about
such constraints: sometimes, they seem real and binding until they suddenly disappear; the art of
politics entails persuading others that something that might seem economically and politically
22
There is some controversy about whether it is appropriate to use loss aversion to analyze welfare
implications of alternative policies. Kahneman, Wakker and Sarin (1997) emphasize the difference between
“Decision Utility” and “Experienced Utility.” While loss aversion may correctly capture the weights humans
put on decisions, it may not capture “Experienced Utility” well.
12
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
infeasible in fact is feasible.
23
There are two real aspects of political decision-making that cannot not be ignored. The first is time
consistency. Time consistency problems arise whenever there are long term decisions, and as
such are particularly pertinent to innovation: The government has an incentive to persuade the
private sector to develop low carbon technologies, but once developed, the marginal social cost of
carbon might decrease, thus allowing it to charge a low carbon price. But at a low carbon price, the
development of the new technology would not have made sense. Of course, if private agents view
governments as having a time consistency problem, the initially announced price or regulatory path
will not be viewed as credible, and therefore will not have the desired effect. (Helm et al 2003).
Here’s where the second, and often neglected, aspect of political economy enters: policies today
can affect the coalitions that form and agents’ behavior (investments) in such a way that their future
interests are changed; and this may alter the political support for policies in the future. Indeed, this
was part of the rationale for the Paris strategy: if enough firms believed that there was enough
global commitment to climate change that there would be a high carbon price (implicit or explicit)
going forward, they would have an incentive to make green investments; and to ensure that they
were advantaged over firms that didn’t make such investments and to ensure that they obtained the
desired returns on those investments, they would then politically support, in coalition with other like-
minded agents, a high carbon price.
24
23
Sometimes, the political constraints are another way of saying, “if we could only ignore issues of
distribution.” But of course we can’t. Distributive consequences are of first order importance.
Earlier, we referred to the distributive issues raised by horizontal inequities. Government policies creating
horizontal inequities are sometimes viewed as unacceptableeven though when such disparities are created
by the market they seem acceptable. Thus, it may be viewed as “unfair” and therefore unacceptable for
government to impose a carbon tax that hurts those who have to drive to work, even though an increase in the
oil price that would have the identical effect is accepted. The reason may be the seeming anonymity of market
forces while it is often difficult to evaluate the true motives and rationale behind government policies. In
contrast, it is possible, and perhaps even plausible, that non-drivers might get together in a political process to
advantage themselves at the expense of drivers.
24
There is a fixed cost associated with forming coalitions; and the formation of such coalitions is like a public
good. Once established, the coalitions can be self-sustaining, and result in the continuation of the policies. For
an earlier discussion, see Stiglitz (1998b).
More generally, there can be a multiplicity of such political/economic equilibria. See Hoff and Stiglitz (2004,
2007), who study a transition from a “lawless” state to one governed by a rule of law in the context of the
transition from Communism to a market economy. There are obvious analytic parallels between that
transition and the transition from a high-carbon (where there is a dearth of rules governing carbon
emissions) to a low- carbon economy.
At least partial time consistency can be obtained even in a contestable democracy, where future
governments may not fully share preferences (values) and the current government cannot fully commit future
governments to any course of action. Investments both in the private and public sectors are, for instance,
reversible but only partially so, especially in the short run. Even reversible policies (e.g. a change in tax rates)
can lead to only partially reversible actions (i.e. long-term investments), and these can affect both future
patterns of voting and behavior.
See Korinek and Stiglitz (2008, 2009) for a discussion of the general theory in the context of a game
theoretic model with two parties and an application.
13
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
Time consistency, and questions about whether there is a political resolution, enter repeatedly in
policy analysis. In multiple contexts, a policy is described which grows the economic pie, so
everyone could be made better off. But that’s far different from a policy that will make everyone
better off. Even if government engages in compensatory actions today so that everyone is better
off now, it may be difficult for the government to commit itself to sustaining those compensatory
policies.
25
Moving beyond the “single price in all uses, at all dates, and at all places” increases the
set of feasible policies, and thus the prospect of finding a policy that avoids politically
unacceptable redistributive effects in a time-consistent way.
1. Distribution
A central reason, we have argued, for going beyond a single carbon price relates to distribution.
Changes in prices, regulations, and government investments each can have large redistributive
effects. There may be large costs associated with undoing the distributional effects, and, given
limitations in information available to government, the adverse effects on distribution may not be
able to be undone and, in any case, can never be undone perfectly and costlessly. The question on
which we focus in this section is whether there may be regulations and/or more complex pricing
policies that achieve similar environmental goals as a simple carbon tax with fewer adverse
distributive consequences. Though regulations might not be first best, i.e. would not be chosen if
redistributions were costless, once the costs of redistributions are taken into account, they are
socially desirable.
26
Throughout the analysis of this section, we assume there is a carbon tax. We
show, however, that under certain circumstances, regulations
27
may reduce the general level of the
carbon tax required to achieve a given reduction in carbon emissions, reduce the magnitude of the
resulting adverse distribution, and as a consequence, increase societal welfare.
25
For a discussion in the context of globalization and technical change, see Korinek and Stiglitz, 2019.
26
We emphasize that this is a theoretical exercise. We are not evaluating the relative merits of any particular
regulatory measure designed to supplement a carbon tax.
27
or differential carbon taxes in different usages
14
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
1.1. A Simple Model
We begin by ignoring uncertainty and dynamics, focusing simply on the question of the best way to
achieve, for example, a given reduction in carbon.
28
Figure 1A illustrates the carbon tax that achieves
the given level of carbon emissions, with the level of carbon emissions falling as the carbon price
increases. Assume there is some important sector j, which is very carbon intensive and such that for
that sector, a switch to a low carbon-intensive production technology only occurs at a very high
carbon price.
29
We identify a switching price, p*, at which it switches to a low carbon technology.
The switching price p* determines the carbon price required to achieve emission levels of E*; at a
price below p*, the level of carbon emissions exceeds the desired level.
Figure 1
28
As we have emphasized, the amount of reduction that is desirable is itself an endogenous variable in a fuller
analysis.
29
This formulation biases the analysis towards a regulatory intervention, since it assumes there is a well-
defined, easily identifiable low emissions technology. In practice, as we note below, there are a myriad of
decisions that affect emissions. The Stern-Stiglitz Commission recommended combining regulations with
prices. Regulations can, for instance, proscribe coal burning electric generation; the prices will help induce
low emission choices within.
15
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
Figure 2
Societal welfare (apart from the benefits of carbon reduction) is denoted by the indirect social
welfare function W = aR V
R
(q, q
j
, YR) + (1 - aR) V
NR
(q, q
j
, YNR) where q
j
is the price of the jth good
and q is the price of all other goods, V
R
and V
NR
being the indirect utility of the rich and non-rich
respectively, YR and YNR the income of the rich and non-rich respectively, aR the social weight put
on the rich, with
30
Vqj = -C
j
VY and Vq = -C VY where C
j
and C are consumption in the carbon-
intensive sectors and of all other goods, respectively (where for convenience we have dropped the
subscript denoting the group), and VY is the marginal utility of income.
31
32
Now assume instead of relying just on prices, we introduce a regulation for sector j that requires
producers to use the very low carbon technology. This shifts the supply curve of carbon, as
depicted in figure 1A, so that the target emissions level can now be achieved at a low carbon price
p’ < p*. The constraint imposes an implicit higher shadow price on carbon in sector j: The effective
shadow price of carbon in j (at least with respect to its choice of technology) is p*, higher than p’.
This is the sense in which the regulation violates the principle of one price. Of course, sector j uses
a “too low” carbon technology relative to the carbon price p’; and it is the lower carbon intensity in
that sector that allows for the carbon budget to be satisfied at a lower price. With the regulation in
place, p’ is the price of carbon that achieves the desired reduction in carbon. At carbon price p’, the
30
These are standard results concerning indirect utility functions.
31
We can explicitly incorporate loss aversion by writing the welfare function as depending on current prices po:
+ -
V(p – po,…. ), with |Vp | > |Vp |, i.e. the loss from an increase in price above the current level is greater than the
gain from a fall in the price.
32
Throughout this simplified analysis, incomes are kept constant, except that the proceeds of the tax
are redistributed as a uniform lump sum.
16
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
cost of production of sector j would be lower at any choice of technique than at p* simply because
of the lower carbon price, but in total, higher than it would be without the regulation because of the
constraint of being forced to use the low carbon technology. In effect, while sector j confronts a
higher carbon price, it gets a lump-sum rebate on the difference between p’ and p*.
All products (with carbon emissions), with the exception of j, now have a lower price q than without
regulations, and on that account societal welfare is higher
33
. Of course, the regulation has
increased the cost of production in sector j, increased output prices in that sector, and introduced a
distortion in the economy. On these accounts, societal welfare is lower. It is possible, however, that
the former effect on social welfare outweighs the latter.
Carbon tax revenues are lower, by the amount (p* - p’) x E, where E is the level of emissions. The
move from carbon prices p* to the regulation combined with carbon price p’ leads to a change in
consumer prices from {q*, q*
j
} to {q’, q’
j
}.
34
If we ignore distribution, the increase in
utility from lower carbon prices is (from the indirect utility function) approximately
𝑉𝑉
Y {(q* - q’) x C +
(q*
j
- q
j
) C
j
} (where
𝑉𝑉
y aR V
R
Y(q, q
j
, YR) + (1 - aR) V
NR
Y(q, q
j
, YNR) ), which, if the shadow price of
a dollar in the public sector is not too different from that in the private (so that
𝑉𝑉
Y 1),
is approximately equal to the difference in tax revenues, in a competitive economy with zero profits
where the change in the value of output equals the change in the cost of production, the payments
of carbon taxes plus the additional costs of production resulting from the regulation. But going
beyond an infinitesimal tax, the gain in consumer surplus from the lowering of q is strictly less than
the loss in welfare from the distortionary regulation plus the loss in tax revenue: there is a
deadweight loss.
35
That is the essence of the Diamond-Mirrlees results on the desirability of
production efficiency (the use of a single price in production.) If only efficiency were the issue (and
there were no other second-best considerations), carbon pricing would thus be preferable.
1.1.1. Direct distributional effects
There are, however, both direct and indirect distributional impacts of a carbon tax. For simplicity,
assume that the proceeds of the tax are used to reduce proportionately income taxes. If those who
33
Even apart from any benefit from lower carbon emissions.
34
For simplicity, we assume constant returns to scale technologies, so there are no pure profits/rents.
35
Illustrated in figure 1B by the shaded area.
17
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
consume commodity j are disproportionately rich and those who consume the other goods are
disproportionately poor, then the “tax-cum-regulatory” system imposes more of the adjustment
burden on the rich and less on the poor, so that social welfare, as measured by the change in aR VR
+ (1 - aR) VNR, increases so long as the proceeds of the carbon tax at the margin are not distributed
too progressively (that is, so long as the reduction in revenues from the lowering of the carbon tax
doesn’t have too regressive effects). The tax- cum-regulatory policy drives down the overall carbon
price, even if it creates an inefficiency, centered on good j. Hence the incidence of the tax-cum-
regulatory regime is more on the rich: the rich disproportionately pay the cost of the regulatory
inefficiency, because they consume a lot of j, and the poor bear disproportionately benefit from the
lower carbon price.
36
In short, one has to weigh the distributional benefit against the production distortion to assess the
desirability of the tax-cum-regulatory scheme vs. the pure tax. It is clearly conceivable that the
former is preferred, especially if the carbon saving from the regulation is great and the
distributional impacts are large.
1.1.2. Indirect Distributional Effects
There can also be indirect distributional impacts, as a result of the general equilibrium effects. The
higher carbon tax may have an adverse impact on the relative demand for, say, unskilled labor (for
example, if more carbon-intensive goods, like coal, are more unskilled-labor intensive), lowering
wages of low-income workers. In first-, or even second-best tax theory, the government can provide
a wage subsidy to low-wage workers (in general, and those directly impacted in particular
37
) that
would offset this adverse distributional effect. Again, however, in practice implementing these
additional subsidies is costly.
Indeed, implementing the offsetting subsidies may not even be feasible, given the limited
information available to the government, which cannot monitor either effort or hours worked, the
standard assumption in the theory of optimal taxation.
38
Though any equalitarian social welfare
36
Tax revenues decrease (a lower carbon tax times the same target level of carbon), necessitating a reduction
in public expenditures (redistributions) or an increase in taxes elsewhere. If, for instance, there is a uniform
increase in income tax rates, for the poor, the gains in the reduction in the carbon tax are greater than the
losses from the increase in income taxes.
37
Because of imperfections in labor mobility, adverse effects on those directly impacted are likely to be greater
than on labor more generally.
38
Thus, an individual may be a low-income worker because he is low ability, or because he is high ability but is
exerting little effort or working fewer hours. If the government could monitor effort and hours worked, it
could infer ability and impose a first-best lump-sum tax. See Mirrlees (1971).
18
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
function would like to distinguish among workers of different abilities, making such distinctions is
costly and imperfect, and this is so whether one relies on self-selection mechanisms or direct
screening mechanisms. As a result, policies that increase inequality in wages (the disparity between
wages of skilled and unskilled workers) lower social welfare (Stiglitz (2018b)).
Whether the general equilibrium impact of a carbon tax is to lower wages of unskilled workers is an
empirical question that may be hard to answer. It may reduce the demand for coal (emphasized by
the Trump administration) and thus of coal miners, but it may also increase the demand for unskilled
solar panel installers and thus increase (relative) wages of unskilled workers. Data suggest that for
the US, the increase in demand for solar panel installers is greater than the loss in demand for coal
miners, and if this pattern holds more generally, a carbon tax would be even more desirable than it
would have been in the absence of these distribution effects.
39
This example illustrates an important aspect of responding to the distributive impacts of a carbon
tax: When there are an easily identifiable set of losers, it may be easier to design offsetting
measures than when the population of losers is more diffuse. Identifying coal miners and designing
policies to limit their losses may be relatively easy compared to identifying those consumers who
disproportionately are adversely affected by a high carbon price.
1.1.3. Horizontal inequities
A very high carbon tax leads to horizontal differences among consumers who previously were
similarly situated. Those who consume disproportionately more carbon goods are worse off. Thus,
poor owners of carbon-inefficient vehicles who must use them extensively see the possibility that
their real incomes will fall, and the value of one of their few assets, their vehicles, will decline as
well.
The essential problem is that there is no way of compensating the high-carbon consumers that does
not undo the objective of the carbon tax, which is to discourage consumption of carbon- intensive
goods. Assume, arguendo, that the government could observe the consumption patterns of each
individual. It can then identify the individuals who are consuming high levels of carbon-intensive
39
See Wei, Patadia, and Kammen (2010). Patrizio et al. (2018) describe how a well-designed “bio-energy with
carbon capture and storage” (BECCS) strategy can actually preserve large numbers of jobs in the coal
industry.
19
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
goods. But attempts to offset the loss of welfare with a grant based on their carbon consumption is,
effectively, undoing the carbon tax. Only if it could see deep into the soul of the individual and
ascertain who was a high-carbon consumer without looking at behavior could it accomplish the
necessary redistribution within the framework of a carbon tax. This is clearly impossible.
40
The issue just described increases in importance the larger the carbon tax, the larger the
disparities in consumption patterns (which may be related both to income disparities and
population heterogeneity) and the greater the societal loss aversion.
1.1.4. Uncertainty about incidence, Horizontal Inequities and a Preference for a Smaller
Carbon Tax
There is a further, related set of arguments in favor of a mix of policies that include regulations with
an implicit higher carbon tax in some uses, but results in a smaller carbon tax overall.
41
Assume, as in
the previous paragraphs, that there is unobservable individual heterogeneity making it impossible
for government to compensate each individual for the carbon tax he has paid. All that can be done
is to compensate the average individual. The individual himself may not know enough about the set
of available technologies ex ante to know the magnitude of the price increases to be expected at
each level of carbon price. But ex ante, the imposition of a carbon tax can be thought of as mean
income preserving spread, in the sense that, on average, all of the income collected will be paid
back, but that will not be true for any particular individual, who may get back more or less than she
paid. It should be clear that if individuals are sufficiently risk (or loss) averse, then all individuals
might oppose the carbon tax because their expected utility, taking into account the uncertain
40
That is, the only signal that high-carbon preference individuals are deserving of additional compensation is
their consumption of carbon-intensive goods. Using that as a basis of compensation would, of course, undo
the effects of the carbon tax.
41
The distinction between the discussion of this section and our earlier discussion of individual heterogeneity is
this: the earlier discussion focused on the consequences for social welfare of the inability to offset the
differential effects on different individuals; here we focus on the fact that individuals themselves may now
know enough about the structure of the economy to be able to predict the consequences of a particular
policy on their own well- being. (In the former model, individuals understood the consequences, but the
government couldn’t ascertain who was affected in which way). This uncertainty about the
consequences of a policy change means that individuals’ ex ante expected utility is lowerit has a social
cost. It can also have political consequences: it can (rationally) lead to opposition to the policy change.
20
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
incidence
42
, is lower. And the greater the carbon tax, the greater the loss in welfare.
43
In some
cases, where there is an explicit green technologyrenewable energyone may be able to induce
the switch to the “greener” technology more efficiently, with less redistributive consequences and
with less uncertainty, through a subsidy for a particular class of technologies or a regulation than
through a general carbon tax.
44
So too, there may be more uncertainty associated with the consequences of a carbon tax than with
that of particular regulations. This is the case, for instance, for a regulation that specified a particular
alternative technology, with a predictable impact on costs through the economic system. This may
be the case even for the government. There is what has been called in other contexts instrument
uncertainty
45
.
A regulation that simply specifies the use of the low emissions technology (when such a
technology can be identified) may, accordingly, be preferable to the use of a sector-specific
carbon emissions tax.
46
Thus, a portfolio of actions entailing “low uncertainty regulations” and
“a relative low carbon tax” can, in terms of ex ante expected utility, be preferred to just a
carbon tax (yielding the same expected reduction in carbon emissions) by all individuals.
1.1.5. Alternative ways of achieving carbon reductions consistent with distributional
objectives
A natural question is, are there other ways of achieving carbon reductions consistent with
distributional objectives? The government might, for instance, subsidize the consumption of the
non-j goods and tax the consumption of j, achieving the same consumption prices and therefore
42
That there is such uncertainty is obvious: economists disagree markedly over tax incidence.
43
There may be still greater uncertainty because of the possibility of new technologies being introduced as a
result of a carbon tax. The next section will deal explicitly with induced innovation.
44
Instrument uncertainty may lead to the preference for sectoral regulatory measures rather than sectoral
specific taxes, as the next paragraph illustrates. See, however, the discussion elsewhere in this paper,
including at the end of section 3.1.6., on the benefits of combining price and regulatory mechanisms.
45
For instance, the government may not be sure of the level of carbon tax required to achieve, say, the Paris
goals, or precisely what price of carbon will induce the use of the low emissions technology, in the example
earlier in this section. Instrument uncertainty matters: there is a societal cost (in additional distortions in the
price of the jth good) in imposing a tax beyond the necessary level. A government commitment to obtaining
that objective through a carbon tax may impose a high level of risk on consumers and producers.
In the context of macroeconomics, the role of instrument uncertainty in affecting the desirability of price vs.
quantity measures has been discussed in Greenwald and Stiglitz (1989). See Hepburn (2006) for a review on
instrument choice under uncertainty. Risk can be mitigated by the kinds of “safety valve” measures
discussed in section 5.1.
46
It is straightforward to formalize the losses associated with these uncertainties and to compare the
consequences of the use of a price vs. a regulatory intervention.
21
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
the same distributional effects. Even this intervention violates the “one price of carbon for all
uses,” but at least it entails a price rather than a regulatory intervention.
47
Of course, in the absence of uncertainty and transaction costs, and with perfect information, one
can achieve identical outcomes through either tax or regulatory interventions.
48
But the solution
entailing taxes with offsetting subsidies is more complicated: every sector except j faces both a
carbon tax and a consumption subsidy, and the jth sector faces a carbon tax and a consumption
tax.
While this section has emphasized the use of regulatory measures to complement a carbon tax to
enable lowering the level of the carbon tax, there are other actions the government can take with
similar effects. Any public investment, zoning regulation, or other public action that results in a shift
to the left in the overall supply of carbon at any carbon price lowers the requisite carbon price. The
“single carbon price” rule might suggest that in all of its public investment and regulatory decisions,
the government evaluates alternatives using that carbon price. This analysis suggests that for
certain investment or regulatory decisions, it may want to use a higher shadow price if there are
“favorable” distributive benefits, either directly or indirectly, as a result of the lower carbon price. A
greater investment in public transportation might thus be doubly desirable, being particularly
beneficial for the poor, and at the same time enabling the equilibrium price of carbon to be lower
than it otherwise would have been.
49
1.1.6. Putting the result in perspective
As we noted in the introduction, the result just derived can be viewed as a specific application of a
more general result in the theory of optimal taxation and expenditures: when there are distributive
effects that cannot be undone by commodity taxes (including type specific factor subsidies),
47
Some of the public discourse concerning fuel standards revolves around similar issues: for instance, some
have suggested that lowering fuel standards would have a positive distributional effect (Holland, Hughes,
Knittel, 2009), though we noted earlier that transport may be one sector in which increasing energy prices
would have a positive distributional effect.
For an earlier discussion of how to make a carbon tax reform progressive, see Klenert and Mattauch, 2016.
48
This is a general result: under these conditions, there is no compelling case against regulation and for price
interventions. It is only when one introduces imperfect and asymmetric information, uncertainty, and
transactions cost that one can argue for one instrument over another. But when this is done formally, the case
for price interventions is typically less compelling than economists have assumed. See, e.g., Weitzman (1974,
1977) and the more extensive discussion in section 5.
49
This argument follows that of Stiglitz (2018b), which also analyzes the distributive implications of public
investment, showing the desirability of the use of differential shadow prices.
22
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
production efficiency is in general not desirable.
50
Here, it would be desirable to tax carbon
emissions in the jth sector at a higher rate. This would be the case even if there were a continuous
technology choice in the jth sector. There are instances in which this can be (and has been) done:
we can charge a higher price for aviation fuel (consumed more by the rich) than for gasoline. More
generally, if we can identify a set of goods which are more carbon intensive and more consumed by
the rich, it would be desirable to impose higher taxes (including higher carbon taxes) on these
goods. And the same holds for intermediate goods which are used in the production of final goods
which are consumed disproportionately by the rich.
The discrete change in technology in sector j (and thus of emissions) might, of course, naturally lead
to a “corner” solution, where the tax is set at just the level to induce the lower level of emissions.
Further increases in the jth sector carbon tax would yield lower marginal benefits.
51
If that were all that there were to the matter, we could achieve the result either by a regulation or a
sector specific carbon tax set at the level to just induce the use of the low emission technology. But
in practice, matters are more complicated. Because the critical tax may differ from firm to firm, a
different tax would have to be set for each firm. And because the critical tax might differ over time,
it would have to be continuously reset.
In many cases, however, there are multiple subtle choices concerning techniques of production, and
implementing separate regulations for each of these may be virtually impossible. To induce firms to
make the right choices, one has to rely on the use of a carbon price. This argues for combining
regulations with carbon prices, as the Stern-Stiglitz Report advocates.
52
50
As we noted earlier, this holds too if there are other restrictions on taxation, e.g. on profits and rent taxes,
especially if these restrictions have distributive consequences.
51
The optimal tax problem is beset by non-convexities and discontinuities, as Mirrlees (1971) and much of the
subsequent literature has recognized. See, e.g. Arnott and Stiglitz (1988).
52
Recall our earlier discussion focusing on problems associated with implementation and instrument
uncertainty. There is a related point of regulatory circumvention: innovations which comply with the
regulation but are less effective in reducing carbon. It may be difficult for the government to continuously
adapt the regulations in response to changing technology. This is not the case, however, for regulations that
focus directly on emission levels.
23
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
3.2. Some Political economy concerns
Not surprisingly, there are political consequences arising from the possibility of adverse
(uncompensated) distributional effects.
53
Individuals are particularly sensitive to high new taxes
(consistent with the theory of loss aversion), and political discourse often centers on the individuals
who are likely to be hurt. Large losers from a carbon tax will campaign against the carbon tax. As
we noted earlier, there is typically uncertainty about the ultimate effect of a tax, and thus large
numbers of individuals, even possibly a majority, may face a lowering of their ex ante expected
utility, and thus oppose even a tax with lump sum rebates. The regulation, by keeping the carbon
tax to a lower level, reduces the distributive effects, except for those associated with sector j, and
may accordingly mitigate these adverse political effects.
54
Thus the tax-cum-regulatory policy may
be (more) politically robust.
Moreover, both among recipients and non-recipients of subsidies, there may be beliefs (rational or
irrational) concerning what are acceptable and non-acceptable subsidies, taxes, and regulations, all
of which are particularly relevant to the political economy of carbon taxation. It may be acceptable
to have a hidden subsidy to coal, which leads to higher wages of coal miners, but unacceptable to
give coal miners an explicit pay check. (Behind views of what is and is not acceptable are
“narratives”: coal protection may be justified because it is protecting the industry against unfair
competition from abroad, while outright subsidies are seen simply as handouts. And the objection
to handouts may not just be “moral,” but politicalwhere do we draw the line in who gets
handouts?) While from an analytical perspective, there may be limited or no difference amongst
these alternatives, behavioral economics has shown that framing and perceptions matter. Thus, it
may be acceptable to stop firms that impose large costs on others (big polluters) through regulation,
but not acceptable to “allow” them to pollute, simply by paying a price to do so.
55
Among
environmentalists, a standard criticism of an environmental tax is that it allows those with money to
destroy the environment: it puts a price on something that should be priceless.
53
Even when there are compensations, as we noted in section I, voters may not believe that there can be a
credible commitment to the continuation of such subsidies. Preventing time inconsistencies in this arena may
be more difficult than in the context of investments, described elsewhere in this paper.
54
Because sector j is (by assumption) a sector that is disproportionately consumed by the rich, the distributive
impacts may be politically “welcome,” and even more so if that sector has a high level of carbon emissions. It
will have political legitimacy.
55
See Sandel (2012) and Bowles and Polania-Reyes (2012). For a somewhat contrasting view, see Caney and
Hepburn (2011). Klenert et al. (2018) emphasize the importance of framing policy proposals in ways that
generate political acceptability
24
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
3.2.1. Andogenous Preferences and Behavioral Economics
In doing so, it changes attitudes towards the environment and its protection; it can change
preferences in a fundamental way. As we noted earlier, a recent strand of behavioral economics
has emphasized the determination of “deep preferences,” what individuals actually care about.
While there has not been much research into the relative impact of prices vs. regulations in changing
“deep preferences,”
56
from what has been observed in other contexts, putting a price on the
environment may make it more acceptable to “abuse” it, i.e. to engage in emissions, while strong
regulatory constraints may help create a norm of protecting the environment.
Similarly, in many countries, for instance, there has been a change in attitudes about the use of
plastics, and especially plastic bags, a change in which grocery store policies may have played an
important role, as they increasingly switched to paper and reusable bags. The switch had salience.
It was an everyday reminder of the importance of the environment, and it thereby helped reinforce
pro-environment attitudes and values. Even when grocery stores started charging for plastic bags to
induce the switch, it was welcomea sign that the store was environmentally sensitiverather than
greeted with the hostility that it would have received a quarter century ago. In turn, the use of paper
bags helped spread a culture of environmental sensitivity. In these cases it was a small price
(though from some perspectives, going from a free bag to charging a few pennies is a large change)
that induced changes in behavior, leading in turn to changes in norms, while in other countries, it
was regulations that brought about the social change. Regulations moving the economy towards
green light bulbs, for instance, might shift consumption patterns far faster than a change in price.
57
Social coordinationcreating new normsmay not be optimized by changes in prices, partly
because such changes in prices do not in general signify changes in norms. By contrast, a
regulatory induced change to paper bags and green light bulbs more clearly reflects a new societal
norm.
56
There is some recent research on the behavioral impact of carbon taxes. Similar to the day-care experiment,
Lanz et al. (2018) show experimental evidence on how carbon taxes can crowd out pro-social motivation to
consume less carbon-intensive products. Mattauch, Hepburn and Stern (2018) provide a framework to adjust
carbon taxes taking into account such change in social preferences. While these analyze the behavioral
impact of carbon taxes, there is no evidence on relative impact on behavior of a carbon tax vis-à-vis
regulation.
57
This may be particularly true in those instances where it is hard to explain consumption patterns on the
basis of models of economic rationality, e.g. individuals could save money by switching to greener products.
25
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
For all these reasons, the combination of regulations and prices might be preferable on both
utilitarian and political economy grounds.
3.2.2. Diffuse vs. concentrated costs
But countering these political economy arguments are those that go in the opposite direction: while
the impacts of general carbon taxes are diffuse, those of a regulation (e.g. on sector j) are more
concentrated, and a standard political economy argument holds that the problem of the “public
good” of lobbying is more easily overcome when impacts are concentrated, i.e. there will be
lobbying by the jth sector to water down the regulations and to make sure that they do not keep
pace with changes in technology. On the other hand, with some industries so much more polluting
than others, and therefore more affected even by a uniform carbon tax, these high polluting
industries have an incentive to lobby against any carbon tax at a significant rate or for an exemption
for their industry, greatly weakening the effectiveness of carbon pricing. In their campaign against
the tax, they will, of course, emphasize adverse effects on ordinary individuals. In many countries
such an unholy alliance has been able to stymie green policies. Especially as the importance of
climate change has come to be generally recognized, seemingly distributionally sensitive green
policies, with regulations targeted at the worst offender, may garner more political support.
Some have argued that by linking the carbon tax with a uniform direct dividend of the revenues
received one can change the political economy of the carbon tax. Such a policy would, on average,
be strongly redistributive, and many have argued that somehow, this form of redistribution would be
acceptable (because it is associated with the public good of reducing carbon emissions) when
comparable redistributions would not be. These alleged political economy advantages, proponents
claim, more than outweigh the inefficiency associated with provided lump sum payments to the
household sector combined with distortionary taxation to recover the revenues lost, that might
otherwise have been spent, say, on green infrastructure.
There is another political argument in support of a carbon tax with proceeds redistributed as lump
sum payments: It could simultaneously garner support of both progressives with equalitarian social
26
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
preferences and conservatives with a procedural preference for markets, who see the tax as
avoiding heavy-handed government interventions.
58
2. Innovation
The nature of the optimal price path is a subject of some controversy, with some arguing for a slow
path of price increase, giving time for individuals to adjust; some suggesting that optimal
(discounted) prices being the same over time, and others arguing for a fast pathor even a higher
price in the short run than the long
59
. The Stern-Stiglitz Commission itself seemed somewhat
agnostic on the issue, though it called attention to both the importance of adjustment costs and
innovation:
“Efficient carbon-price trajectories begin with a strong price signal in the present and a
credible commitment to maintain prices high enough in the future to deliver the required
changes. Relatively high prices today may be more effective in driving the needed changes
and may not require large future increases, but they may also impose higher, short-term
adjustment costs. In the medium to long term, explicit price trajectories may need to be
adjusted based on the experience with technology development and the responsiveness
to policy. The policy dynamics should be designed to both induce learning and elicit a
response to new knowledge and lessons learned.
Price adjustment processes should be transparent to reduce the degree of policy
uncertainty...”
The objective of the discussion here is to develop a better understanding of the argument for a
trajectory with a particularly high price in the short run to spur innovation. (Note that the previous
section focused on the overall level of carbon pricesarguing that the use of regulations may allow
the carbon price to be set at a lower level than otherwise. Here, we are concerned with the
trajectory of prices, given a particular set of regulations, that is, whether optimal prices increase or
decrease over time. Analogous issues arises with the time trajectory of regulations.)
60
58
This argument is, of course, far more salient in some countries, like the United States, than in others.
59
See Sinclair (1992, 1994) and Ulph and Ulph (1994) for an early discussion.
60
Space limitations do not allow us to consider the relative merits of prices vs. regulations in inducing
innovation. There is, however, a direct analogue to the question posed here: the trajectory of regulation, i.e.
27
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
The argument for the middle positiona constant price in today’s dollars, which entails prices
increasing exponentially at the rate of interestis, as we noted earlier, derived from the nature of
climate change itself. More generally, there is some smooth increase in expected marginal damage
per ton as cumulative emissions increase. While the shadow price is not an explicit function of time,
it is an explicit function of cumulative emissions, which is itself a function of time. As we approach
the limiting situation, where we are able to contain increases in atmospheric carbon concentrations,
then the (discounted) price converges to a constant.
Popular discussions focus on politics and adjustment costs. Politically, societies are averse to quick
changes, partially for reasons already given. Moreover, quick changes have large costs of
adjustment. Conventional economic costs of adjustments by themselves cannot justify a time-
varying price: individuals will respond slowly if there is a cost of adjustment. But they need to be
guided in their adjustment by the right shadow prices. But because of the macroeconomic
externalities associated with the adjustment process, the macro dynamic process is not in general
efficient.
61
Moreover, as the previous section explained, individuals themselves may not be sure
about the costs that they will bear in the process of adjustment
62
, and risk and loss aversion might
then result in large majorities opposing any pricing scheme, even if there were, say, lump-sum
rebates that sufficed to compensate the average individual. Achieving an efficient, equitable, and
politically acceptable adjustment process may accordingly entail time- varying priceswith a
presumption that prices adjust slowly to the long-run equilibrium in order to spread the adjustment
costs out over time.
63
at what pace regulatory standards are optimally tightened over time. Regulations can be translated into
shadow prices, and once that is done, the analysis here is directly applicable.
While the overall lower level of carbon prices will induce less innovation in reducing emissions in those sectors,
the regulation in the high carbon sectors, especially if well-designed (e.g. targeted at limiting emissions), can
be very effective in reducing emissions in these sectors. Given the non-convexities associated with research,
it may be efficient to focus research centered on reducing emissions in the high emissions sectors.
61
That is, a firm in laying off a worker (say in response to a high carbon tax making a particular technology
uncompetitive) doesn’t take fully into account the costs imposed on the workers, e.g. in finding a new job,
nor does he take into account the induced unemployment that might result as that worker cutbacks his
consumption. For a broader discussion of macroeconomic externalities, see Jeanne and Korinek (2010).
62
This argument is analogous to the one presented earlier concerning uncertainties associated with the
impacts of a change in the carbon price across individuals.
63
There may, in additional, by intergenerational aspects. The generation in which the aggressive transition to a
green economy begins may bear disproportionately the costs, because of changes in asset values. Slower
transitions modulate the impacts on these asset prices. The generation that is at the onset of a green
transition may bear additional fixed costs in designing new alternative technologies. It is problematic
whether market mechanisms will ensure that these costs will be shared across generations, and it is also
problematic whether government will engage in offsetting intertemporal redistributions.
28
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
Here I want to present an argument to the contrary: that it may be desirable to have a higher carbon
price in the short run than in the long run.
2.1. Learning by doing and inducing a shift in technology
The argument derives from the benefits from innovation that might be induced by a high- carbon
price in the short run, benefits which extend over time. There are large fixed costs of switching
technologies, and only large changes in relative prices can induce a change in technology. Once
that change is effected, there would be large switching costs to return to a high carbon technology,
and especially if there is learning by doing, so that the low carbon technology continues to improve
relative to the high-carbon technology. Learning by doing argues that as a result of using a
technology, there are improvements in its productivity (Arrow, 1962; Stiglitz and Greenwald, 2014).
The theory of localized learning argues that improvements in one technologyfor example, a low-
carbon technologyspill over at best imperfectly to other technologies, say, the high carbon
technology (Atkinson and Stiglitz, 1969, Acemoglou, 2015).
64
This implies that the prices required to
maintain a low carbon economy can be lower than those required to induce a switch.
65
When there are spillovers to others from learning, the benefits of learning will not be fully
appropriated by the parties making the decisions. In making their production decisions, firms won’t
take into account the learning benefits that will not be appropriated by the firm itself. The optimal
carbon price trajectory has to “correct” this externality.
64
In the case of explicit research programs, in principle we could introduce a research subsidy to encourage
“green” research, and some of the earlier literature argued for the use of such a subsidy (as opposed to a
production subsidy) precisely on the grounds we are arguing for here (Acemoglou et al., 2012; Fischer and
Newell, 2008; Gerlagh, Kverndokk and Rosendahl, 2014, and Tvinnereima and Mehling (2018). With learning
by doing, however, there is no explicit research program. It is a by-product of decisions about production,
which are affected by carbon prices. The social value of the learning associated with increased production
implies that there is an additional argument for (early) subsidies of production using the green technology.
The analysis of the following section implies that the magnitude of the green production subsidy may decline
over time. Stiglitz and Greenwald (2014) have emphasized the role of government subsidies in the presence
of such learning spillovers.
65
For a similar result, also exploring the policy implications, including for price trajectories, see Kalkuhl et al.
(2012).
29
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
2.2. A Simple Model: The Theory of Induced Innovation
A simple model that captures and expands on some of the insights of the previous paragraphs is
based on the theory of induced innovation
66
, where firms have a choice between efforts directed at
reducing carbon emissions and labor costs. We model it by assuming output is a function of labor L
and energy E, and innovation makes each unit of labor more productive (labor augmenting
innovation, denoted by an increase in λ) or energy more productive (energy augmenting innovation,
denoted by an increase in µ)
67
in the production function
(3.1) Q = F (µ
t+1
E, λ
t+1
L),
We assume for simplicity that energy use translates directly into carbon emissions. (A more
complicated version of this model would focus both on innovations reducing energy per unit of
output and emissions per unit of energy.) We make use of the well-established concept of the
innovation possibilities curve, postulating that there is a tradeoff between µ and λ, as depicted in
Figure 2: One can only have more energy-augmenting technological progress by giving up on labor-
augmenting technological progress.
68
Figure 3
66
There is an old and distinguished literature, dating back to the work of Fellner (1961), Drandakis and Phelps
(1966), Samuelson (1965), Kennedy (1964), Habakkuk (1962), and more recently revived by Acemoglu (2002,
2010) and Stiglitz (2006, 2014, 2018a). The model developed here is more general and less parametric than
many of the other recent models of induced (or directed) innovation. There are other differences to which we
call attention as we develop the model.
67
While (3.1) does not embed the principle of localized technological progress, it is easy to extend the model to
incorporate this, with each technology having its own value of λ and µ.
68
For simplicity, we have dropped the time superscript.
30
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
We assume each period, the innovation curve is defined relative to the state of knowledge of the
previous period.
We assume a large number of symmetric firms, so each firm takes future period’s wage and energy
costs as given. With a symmetric equilibrium, all firms pursue the same innovation strategy. We
assume that knowledge produced at t for t + 1 becomes publicly available at t + 2. A firm only
focuses on the “private” benefits of innovation, and these occur at time t+1, because after that the
knowledge is public.
69
A standard result in the theory of induced innovation is that the firm chooses the technological
innovation mix which minimizes cost, and the cost-minimizing point is that where the elasticity of
the innovation curve = dln Z/dln λ = relative shares (sL/sE).
70
Innovation is directed at the factor
whose share is relatively large. If the relative labor supply were to diminish, and the elasticity of
substitution between labor and energy were less than one, then the share of labor would increase,
and innovation would be directed more at augmenting labor.
71
The sequence of carbon prices (assumed to increase the cost of energy) thus affects the energy
efficiency at every datean increase in carbon prices at t increases energy efficiency at every
subsequent date. The value of reducing energy (carbon emissions) today is compounded by the
savings in subsequent dates. The market “bias” and level of investment in innovation are inefficient
because the individual firm doesn’t take into account future benefits, since, by assumption, these
innovations move into the public domain the following year.
72
The social value of, say, a percentage reduction in carbon emissions Δ when the shadow price of
carbon emissions is ps (assumed to be fixed at all dates) is ps Δ Ct where Ct is the carbon
emissions at time t. Since the carbon emissions will be converging to zero, the social value of
69
This is a crucial difference between this model and much of the more recent literature, where each
entrepreneur has to solve a complicated intertemporal maximization problem. (In a more fully articulated
version of this model, each entrepreneur would take as given the technological opportunities to be available
in subsequent periods as a result of the innovation by others, and might decide to augment that set by his
own technology. Given the symmetry assumptions, what he does is identical to what others do.)
70
Note, as in the case of learning by doing, that it is the price of carbon as confronted by the firm, that matters.
As we noted earlier, the market distortions that arise here cannot be effectively addressed by having a
general R & D subsidy, though obviously a subsidy limited to energy augmenting innovation would change
the allocation of R & D between energy augmentation and labor augmentation.
71
In some of the older literature (Habakkuk, 1962), it was suggested that innovation was directed at increasing
the productivity of labor because it was “scarce.” This analysis suggests what is relevant is the relative share.
72
More generally, there is no presumption that markets are efficient either in the level of investments in
innovation or in the direction. This is true in virtually any model of innovation. (See Stiglitz and Greenwald,
2014). This is a market failure in addition to the market failure associated with global warming. But it is a
market failure that public policy cannot ignore.
31
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
reduced carbon emissions falls over time. Hence, as we set the market price of carbon to reflect
both the shadow cost of emissions today and the social value of induced innovation, it is clear that
the optimal carbon price falls over time.
73
Obviously, this result depends on the time profile of ps. If the shadow price of carbon is increasing
over time because of increasing concentrations of carbon, then it is possible that
pst Δ Ct might increase for a while. However, at least as we approach the steady state, where
we’ve been able to contain increases in atmospheric carbon concentrations, so pst converges to a
constant, the value of innovation diminishes.
While this argument implies a price trajectory with a high initial price, doing something is better than
doing nothing. The political economyresistance to an initially high carbon taxmay, in the end, be
dispositive.
74
2.3. Behavioral Economics Effects
While the analyses presented so far in this section is based on standard models of innovation with
rational individuals and profit-maximizing firms, there are further arguments for a high initial price of
carbon based on the kinds of behavioral economics considerations discussed at the end of the last
section. One has to engineer a major change in mindset from a fossil fuel economy to a green
economy. Incremental changes in prices may not do that. Large changes do, especially when they
are centered around things that are salient in an individual’s life.
That’s why regulations forcing firms to, say, increase automobile energy efficiency or use green
light bulbs have sometimes proven more effective than price incentives.
75
73
Distributive effects are being ignored, either because there is a lack of concern about distribution or because
there are adequate instruments for undoing the effects. The significance of redistributive effects could also
change over time, reinforcing or offsetting the above conclusion.
74
Countering this political argument is the one made earlier: early investments in green innovation may help
solve the time inconsistency problem, garnering sustained support for green policies.
75
Of course, as always, one has to offset these benefits with the short term distortionary costs that may arise
particularly from a high (implicit) carbon price in a particular sector or against a particular technology. Karplus
et al 2013, for instance, argue that there is a high cost to US vehicle fuel economy standard within a standard
computable general equilibrium model, without innovation and without behavioral economics effects.
32
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
A high early price of carbon may also change the behavior of the fossil fuel industry, inducing them
to explore less for oil, and the resulting higher prices of fossil fuels may help reinforce the move to a
green economy.
76
3. Uncertainty and a Revised Weitzman Price Quantity Perspective
In the context of climate change, there is considerable uncertainty, e.g. about the magnitude of the
links between greenhouse gases and climate change and that of the links between any instrument
and greenhouse gas emissions. The latter uncertainty has led some environmentalists to argue for
quantitative restrictions on emissions. Earlier, Weitzman (1974) delineated conditions under which
such restrictions would be preferable to a simple price intervention.
77
One way of understanding this is to note that while the standard result argues for a single price of
carbon in all places, for all uses, at all dates, the (appropriate shadow) price differ depending on the
state of the world. There is much we don’t know: the effects of any policy on emissions or the effects
of emissions and carbon concentrations on climate change, and the full effects of climate change on
well-being. Thus, as we learn more about the state of the world the carbon price adjusts. In fact, the
best we can do is to announce a carbon price today and a limited state-dependent sequence of
prices going forward. Weitzman’s analysis focused on a one- period world, where either price or
quantity has to be set before we know critical information about the state of the world. The price we
set may be either too high or too low, given the true state of the world; and so, too, for the quantity.
78
Weitzman derives conditions under which if we have to pick either a single price or a single quantity,
picking a quantity would be preferable.
In earlier policy discussion, this debate has loomed large, with many environmentalists arguing for
cap-and-trade because it centers policy on the objective of concern, the level of concentration of
76
In principle, of course, exploration is based on the whole time path of carbon prices, so that seeing (credible)
high future prices leads to less exploration. But there is a large literature suggesting that firms are myopic,
paying more attention to the economics of the moment (today) than possible future scenarios. Moreover, oil
companies may believe that if they succeed in finding large oil deposits, the fear of stranded assets will
curtail the imposition of excessively high carbon prices.
77
See Stiglitz (1986) for a standard textbook treatment.
78
Having a single price for all states of nature is analogous to a restricted tax regime where the same tax rate
has to be imposed on a range of products (in an unrestricted tax regime, every productdistinguished by
every featurewould have its own tax; this is obviously impractical, so, for instance, all automobiles, or all
automobiles of a certain size, face the same tax rate). Dasgupta and Stiglitz (1971) show that when that is the
case, in general, production efficiency may not be desirable, i.e. having just a carbon tax may not be optimal.
33
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
carbon dioxide, and avoids the problems posed by price-instrument uncertainty. The Stern-Stiglitz
report does not weigh into this debate, simply stating
There are different ways to introduce a carbon price. Greenhouse gas (GHG) emissions can be
priced explicitly through a carbon tax or a cap-and-trade system.
As we have noted, the level of climate change and its consequences is of ultimate concern, and
this is related (in an uncertain way) to the concentration of greenhouse gases in the atmosphere.
This in turn is a result of emissions that occur over a long period of time.
Weitzman’s analysis applied to a one-period problem (where welfare was, in effect, related to the
flow of pollutants rather than here, to a stock.) There is not only instrument uncertainty but also
uncertainty about the relationship between atmospheric concentration and social consequences.
The discussion in this section highlights some additional considerations that need to be brought to
bear beyond those highlighted by Weitzman and some of the subsequent research extending his
work into a dynamic context.
As we learn more about the relationship between price (pollutant charge) and emissions
(related, in turn, to the technology of emissions abatement), and about the consequences of
climate change and the relationship between climate change and atmospheric carbon
concentration, the target level of atmospheric concentration to be achieved needs to be
revised.
79
If we use a price mechanism, it means that the price charged is revised. The same,
of course, could be said for the quantities approach. Accordingly, even when the quantities
can be made state dependent, a pure quantities-based framework does not result in perfect
consumption (emissions) smoothing.
The key trade-offs in this dynamic formulation have to do with asymmetries of information, the speed
of government response, the magnitudes of the underlying uncertainties including instrument
uncertainty, and the relative ease (cost) of adjusting prices vs. quantities.
80
Some limiting cases may
be illuminating.
81
79
See Hoel and Karp (2001, 2002) and Pizer (2002).
80
The latter has featured prominently in macroeconomics, where the menu cost literature (Sheshinki and Weiss
(1977), Akerlof and Yellen (1985a, 1985b, and Mankiw (1985)) has emphasized the cost of adjustment of
prices, while other literature has suggested that such costs are not significant, not large enough to explain
macroeconomic fluctuations (Golosov and Lucas, 2007) and stressed adjustment costs and uncertainties
related to quantities (see, e.g. Greenwald and Stiglitz 1989).
81
As Karp and Traeger (2018) observe, in many cases, the choice between price and quantity regimes can,
even in a dynamic setting, be put into a generalized version of Weitzman, where what matters is the relative
34
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
If, for instance, there were no asymmetries of information, no uncertainties about the consequences
of setting a particular price, and government could respond instantaneously as new information
about technology or the consequences of atmospheric concentrations increase by adjusting either
prices or quantities, then (as in the standard one period model) a price and a quantity approach are
equivalent: both are state contingent, and each would be set to generate exactly the same time
profile of emissions and consumption.
If there is no uncertainty about the (expected) marginal social damage of emissions at each date,
then obviously a carbon price reflecting the (expected) marginal social damage of emissions
achieves the optimal results. Assume, however, the government does not have full information on
all the technologies relevant to emissions and emissions abatement.
82
Then in the quantities
approach, the government would, on the basis of its impartial information, have to set forth an
uncertain time path of quantities (to be revised as it learns more about actual emissions). With
bankable caps (at the right interest rate), the price and quantities approaches would, of course, be
equivalentthe private sector in effect using its information to “correct” inappropriate caps set by
the government.
Assume now that there were some clear threshold above which climate change was intolerable (but
below which it was manageable), so that we had a clear target for atmospheric carbon
concentrations, but again the government has less information about abatement technology than the
private sector.
83
Then, with the quantities approach, we can use the market for “price discovery,” to
ascertain the efficient way of achieving this goal, provided we have bankable caps. (Similar results
hold if the government is less informed about the social damage function. This can be particularly
important when there are lags in government policy.) Especially with bankable caps (in a system of
quantity controls), an event today that is rationally anticipated to lead to more stringent controls and
a higher market price for carbon in the future will affect markets and behavior before the
slopes of the marginal damage and marginal cost curves. The discussion below will highlight some of the
special assumptions underlying their analysis.
There is one more dimension of optimal intergenerational policies that has perhaps received insufficient
attention but which we will not be able to pursue here: intertemporal risk trade-offs. Increasing expected
utility this period by reducing risk may well increase the risk that will have to be borne by future generations.
82
If the government is not certain of current and future abatement cost functions, it can only be certain of the
appropriate marginal social cost of carbon if the social damage function is horizontal.
83
Framing the question this way biases the result: when what we care about is the quantity, it is perhaps no
surprise that a quantity-regime is preferable. The Weitzman prices vs. quantities analysis centers around
situations where we have to ascertain the optimal quantity. Still, the following discussion on the use of
market mechanisms is relevant because it highlights the importance of information asymmetries: in the
absence of such asymmetries, the government could have achieved the desirable quantity trajectory by
setting a trajectory for carbon prices.
35
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
government actually adjusts the level of caps (See Koch et al., 2017). By contrast, with a carbon tax,
in the presence of information and adjustment asymmetries, the anticipation of a higher price of
carbon in the future may result in more pollution today, exacerbating emissions volatility, in what may
be viewed as intertemporal leakages.
84
The efficiency losses of adjustment may thus be lower in a
carbon market than with carbon taxes.
85
Under these assumptions, there is some presumption for
using an auctioned- quantity approach with bankable caps. (An auction avoids the difficult problem
of allocating emission rights, which in turn results in large political economy problems.)
3.1. Towards a More General Framework and Finding the Basis of a Political
Consensus in the Presence of Differences in Beliefs
There is, of course, no reason to restrict ourselves to the limiting cases of prices vs. quantities. One
can introduce a non-linear price schedule, two limiting forms of which are the pure price system
and the pure quantity system.
While the literature on optimal tax interventions has clearly explained the advantages of such more
general systems (Roberts and Spence, 1976; Pizer, 2002), there are also general results suggesting
that under a variety of special, but frequently assumed, conditions linear pricing would be optimal
86
.
The argument that there is a preference for simple systems is also unconvincing: there are simple
piece wise systems. For instance, a quantity system where there is a maximum price and a price
system in which there is a maximum quantity of emissions. Such a system obviously limits the
amount of emissions, charging a very high price if it turns out that the costs of emission reductions
is very high, so that with, say, a moderate price, the level of emissions reductions is not sufficient to
meet what is thought to be the requisite level of emissions reductions
87
.
There is one aspect of these systems with safety values that has not received sufficient attention:
In a world in which individuals have different expectations (beliefs), if appropriately structured, they
84
Thus, it is possible that the private sector has better information not only about the abatement function but
also about the damage function. Even if the private sector has no intrinsic interest in the environment, if it
anticipates that information about the social damage function will eventually be learned by the government,
leading to more stringent controls, it will undertake abatement actions, engaging in emissions smoothing
better than if the government set prices based on its (poorer) information.
85
See also Park, Hepburn, and Keohane (2013).
86
Indeed, under these restrictions, no differential commodity taxation is required at all, and a single carbon
price would suffice to correct the climate externality. (Atkinson and Stiglitz, 1976; Kaplow 1996, 2006; Deaton
1979; Deaton and Stern 1986. These results are, of course, overturned with distributive concerns and
restricted taxation (Stiglitz, 2018b.)
87
See Narassimhan et al. (2018) for a description of similar emissions trading systems in California and in the
Regional Greenhouse Gas Initiative (RGGI).
36
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
can provide the basis of greater consensus.
88
Consider a quantities-based restriction with a safety
valve guaranteeing that the price will not exceed a critical level. Then environmentalists, who are
confident that the quantities target can be met at reasonable cost, can support the safety valve,
precisely because they think it is unlikely to have to be invoked. On the other hand,
businesspeople, whose main concern with the quantities approach is that there is a risk of a very
high implicit tax, can support the measure because that “tail risk” has been eliminated.
CONCLUSIONS
The Stern-Stiglitz report seemingly differed from orthodox economic policy entailing a single carbon
price, for all uses, at all dates, in all places, in all uses by arguing for a more nuanced policy where
carbon prices were supplemented by regulations and other government interventions and might
vary across time, location, and uses. In fact, our report falls squarely with the mainstream of modern
public finance. It is the advocates of a simplistic reliance on carbon taxes who have failed to take on
board the insights of modern economics, which recognize the limitations posed by uncertainty,
imperfect information, imperfect appropriability of investments in innovation, and restrictions on the
sets of instruments available to government. We have attempted to show how, in particular,
concerns about distribution, innovation, and uncertainty could justify the policies advocated in
Stern-Stiglitz report. To be sure, the application of this more nuanced policy is more complicated. It
will require a greater understanding of the structure of the economy and of the distributive effects
of policies than an approach that relies simply on carbon taxes. In particular, we have discussed
countering arguments, for instance, some arguing for a gradual adjustment of carbon prices, others
for a short transition to a high carbon price; some suggesting the political economy advantages of a
carbon tax with proceeds redistributed as a lump sum payment, others suggesting the advantages
of a tax-cum-regulatory regime. Like the Stern-Stiglitz Commission, we have not attempted to
undertake an overall balancing of these contrasting forces: the overall assessment will almost surely
differ across countries and over time.
88
Recent work has highlighted how the behavior of the economic system may differ markedly when individuals
have different beliefs. Explicit and implicit bets among individuals may give rise to what Guzman and Stiglitz
called pseudo-wealthas they engage in bets, they both feel wealthier because they both believe on
average they will win. See Guzman and Stiglitz (2016a, 2016b).
37
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
REFERENCES
Acemoglu, D., “Directed Technical Change,” The Review of Economic Studies, 69(4), October 2002, pp. 781-
809.
2010, "When Does Labor Scarcity Encourage Innovation?" Journal of Political Economy, 118(6),
December, pp. 1037-1078.
2015, ”Localised and Biased Technologies: Atkinson and Stiglitz's New View, Induced Innovations, and
Directed Technological Change,The Economic Journal, 125(583), March, pp. 443463.
Acemoglu, P. Aghion, L. Bursztyn and D. Hemous, “The Environment and Directed Technical Change,” The
American Economic Review, 102(1), February 2012, pp. 131-166.
Akerlof, G. A. and J. L. Yellen, (1985a), "A Near-rational Model of the Business Cycle, with Wage and Price
Intertia," The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 100(5), pp. 823838.
(1985b), "Can Small Deviations from Rationality Make Significant Differences to Economic Equilibria?"
American Economic Review, 75(4), pp. 708720.
Arnott, R. and J. E. Stiglitz, “Randomization with Asymmetric Information,” Rand Journal of Economics, 19(3),
Autumn 1988, pp. 344-362
Arrow, K. J., “The Economic Implications of Learning by Doing,” The Review of Economic Studies, 29(3), June
1962, pp. 155-173.
Atkinson, A. B. and J. E. Stiglitz, “A New View of Technological Change,Economic Journal, 79(315),
September 1969, pp. 573-578.
1972, “The Structure of Indirect Taxation and Economic Efficiency,” Journal of Public
Economics, 1(1), April, pp. 97-119.
1976, “The Design of Tax Structure: Direct Versus Indirect Taxation,” Journal of Public Economics,
6(12) , JulyAugust, pp. 55-75.
1980, Lectures on Public Economics, New York and London : McGraw-Hill Book Company.
Reprinted in 2015, with a new introduction, Princeton: Princeton University Press
Baumol, W. J. and W. Oates, “The Use of Standards and Prices for the Protection of the Environment,” Swedish
Economic Journal, 73(1), March 1971, pp. 42-54.
Bowles, S., “Endogenous Preferences: The Cultural Consequences of Markets and other Economic Institutions,”
Journal of Economic Literature 36(1), March 1998, pp. 75111.
2016, The Moral Economy: Why Good Incentives are No Substitute for Good Citizens, Yale
University Press.
38
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
Bowles and S. Polania-Reyes, “Economic Incentives and Social Preferences: Substitutes or Complements?”
Journal of Economic Literature, 50(2), June 2012, pp. 368-425.
Caney, S. and C. Hepburn, “Carbon Trading: Unethical, Unjust and Ineffective?” Royal Institute of Philosophy
Supplements, 69, October 2011, pp. 201-234.
Dasgupta, P. and J. E. Stiglitz, “Differential Taxation, Public Goods, and Economic Efficiency,” Review of
Economic Studies, 38(2), April 1971, pp. 151-174.
1972, “On Optimal Taxation and Public Production,” Review of Economic Studies, 39(1), January, pp.
87-103.
Deaton, A., “Optimally uniform commodity taxes,” Economics Letters, 2(4), 1979, pp. 357-36.
Deaton and N. Stern, “Optimally Uniform Commodity Taxes, Taste Differences, and Lump-sum Grants,”
Economic Letters, 20(3), December 1986, pp. 263-266.
Diamond, P. and J. A. Mirrlees, “Optimal Taxation and Public Production,” American Economic Review, 61(1),
March 1971, pp. 8-27, 261-278.
Dietz, S. and F. Venmans, “Cumulative Carbon Emissions and Economic Policy: In Search of General
Principles,” Grantham Research Institute on Climate Change and the Environment, Working Paper No. 283,
March 2018.
Drandakis, E. M. and E. R. S. Phelps, "A Model of Induced Invention, Growth, and Distribution," Economic
Journal, 76, December 1966, pp. 832-840.
Fellner, W., “Two Propositions in the Theory of Induced Innovations,” The Economic Journal, 71(282), June
1961, pp. 305-308.
Fischer, C. and R.G. Newell, “Environmental and technology policies for climate mitigation,” Journal of
Environmental Economics and Management 55 (2), 2008, pp. 142-162
Flues, F. and A. Thomas, “The distributional effects of energy taxes,” OECD Taxation Working Papers, No. 23,
OECD Publishing, Paris, 2015.
Geanakoplos, J. and H. Polemarcharkis, “Existence, Regularity, and Constrained Suboptimality of Competitive
Allocations when the Asset Market Is Incomplete,” in W. Heller, R. Starr, and D. Starrett (Eds.), Essays in Honor
of Kenneth Arrow, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, Volume 3, 1986, pp.65-95.
Gerlagh, R., S. Kverndokk and K. Rosendahl, “The optimal time path of clean energy R&D policy when patents
have finite lifetime,” Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 67(1), January 2014, pp. 2-19.
Gintis, H., “Welfare Criteria With Endogenous Preferences: the Economics of Education,” International Economic
Review, 15(2), June, 1974.
Gneezy, U. and A. Rustichini, “Pay Enough or Don't Pay at All,” The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 115(3),
August 2000, pp. 791-810.
Gneezy, S. Meier and P. Rey-Biel, “When and Why Incentives (Don’t) Work to Modify Behavior," Journal of
Economic Perspectives, 25(4), Fall 2011, pp. 191210.
39
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
Golosov, M. and R.E. Lucas Jr., "Menu Costs and Phillips Curves," Journal of Political Economy, 115(2), April
2007, pp. 171199.
Goulder, L. H., M. A. C. Hafstead and R. C. Williams, III, “General Equilibrium Impacts of a Federal Clean Energy
Standard,” American Economic Journal: Economic Policy, 8(2), May 2016, pp. 186218.
Grainger, C.A. and C. D. Kolstad, "Who Pays a Price on Carbon?" Environmental and Resource Economics
46(3), July 2010, pp. 359-376.
Greenwald, B. and J. E. Stiglitz, “Externalities in Economies with Imperfect Information and Incomplete
Markets,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 101(2), May 1986, pp. 229-264.
“Toward a Theory of Rigidities,” American Economic Review, 79(2), May 1989, pp. 364- 69.
Guzman, M. and J. E. Stiglitz, “A Theory of Pseudo-Wealth,” Contemporary Issues in Macroeconomics:
Lessons from The Crisis and Beyond, J. E. Stiglitz and M. Guzman (Eds.), IEA Conference Volume, No.155-II,
Palgrave Macmillan, Houndmills, UK and New York, 2016.
2016, “Psuedo-Wealth and Consumption Fluctuations,” NBER Working Paper No. 22838, November,
and presented at the American Economic Association Meetings, January, 2015.
Habakkuk, H.J., American and British Technology in the Nineteenth Century, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 1962.
Helm, D., C. Hepburn and R. Mash, “Credible Carbon Policy,” Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 19(3), Autumn
2003, pp. 438-450.
Hepburn, C., “Regulation by Prices, Quantities, or Both: A Review of Instrument Choice,” Oxford Review of
Economic Policy, 22(2), July 2006, pp. 226-247.
Hoel, M. and L. Karp, “Taxes and Quotas for a Stock Pollutant with Multiplicative Uncertainty,” Journal of Public
Economics, 82(1), October 2001, pp. 91-114.
2002, “Taxes Versus Quotas for a Stock Pollutant,Resource and Energy Economics 24(4), November,
pp. 367-384.
Hoff, K. and J. E. Stiglitz, “After the Big Bang? Obstacles to the Emergence of the Rule of Law in Post-
Communist Societies,” American Economic Review, 94(3), June 2004, pp. 753 - 763.
2008, “Exiting a Lawless State,” Economic Journal, 118(531), August, pp. 1474-1497.
2016, “Striving for Balance in Economics: Towards a Theory of the Social Determination of Behavior,”
Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 126, June, pp. 2557.
Holland, S. P., J.E. Hughes and C.R. Knittel, “Greenhouse Gas Reductions Under Low Carbon Fuel Standards?”
American Economic Journal: Economic Policy, 1(1), February 2009, pp. 106- 46.
IPCC, 2013: Climate Change 2013: The Physical Science Basis. Contribution of Working Group I to the Fifth
Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (Stocker, T.F., D. Qin, G.-K. Plattner,
40
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
M. Tignor, S.K. Allen, J. Boschung, A. Nauels, Y. Xia, V. Bex and P.M. Midgley [eds.]), Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge U.K. and New York.
Jeanne, O. and A. Korinek, "Excessive Volatility in Capital Flows: A Pigouvian Taxation Approach," American
Economic Review, 100(2), May 2010, pp. 403-07.
Kahneman, D., P. P. Wakker and R. Sarin, “Back to Bentham? Explorations of Experienced Utility,” The
Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112(2), May 1997, pp. 375-406.
Kalkuhl, M., O. Edenhofer and K. Lessmann, “Learning or Lock-in: Optimal Technology Policies to Support
Mitigation,” Resource and Energy Economics, 34(1), January 2012, pp. 123.
Karp, L., and C. Traeger, “Prices versus Quantities Reassessed,” CESifo Working Paper Series 7331,
November, 2018.
Karplus, V. J., S. Paltsev, M. Babiker and J. M. Reilly, “Should a vehicle fuel economy standard be combined
with an economy-wide greenhouse gas emissions constraint? Implications for energy and climate policy in the
United States,Energy Economics, 36, March 2013, pp. 322333.
Kaplow, L., “The Optimal Supply of Public Goods and the Distortionary Cost of Taxation,” National Tax Journal,
49(4), December 1996, pp. 51333.
2006, “Optimal Control of Externalities in the Presence of Income Taxation,” NBER Working
Paper 12339, June.
Kennedy, C., “Induced Bias in Innovation and the Theory of Distribution,” The Economic Journal, 74(295),
September 1964, pp. 541-547.
Klenert, D., L. Mattauch, E. Combet, O. Edenhofer, C. Hepburn, R. Rafaty and N. Stern, “Making Carbon Pricing
Work for Citizens,” Nature Climate Change, 8(8), August 2018, pp. 669677.
Klenert and L. Mattauch, “How to Make a Carbon Tax Reform Progressive: The Role of Subsistence
Consumption,” Economics Letters, 138, January 2016, pp. 100-103.
Korinek, A. and J. E. Stiglitz, “Political Economy in a Contestable Democracy: The Case of Dividend
Taxation,”2008 Meeting Papers, Society for Economic Dynamics.
2009, “Dividend Taxation and Intertemporal Tax Arbitrage,” Journal of Public Economics, 93(1-2),
February, pp. 142-159.
2019, “Artificial Intelligence, Worker-Replacing Technological Progress and Income Distribution,” in
Economics of Artificial Intelligence, NBER/University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Kverndokk, S. and K. E. Rosendahl, “Climate Policies and Learning by Doing: Impacts and Timing of
Technology Subsidies,” Resource and Energy Economics, 29(1), January 2007, pp 5882.
Lanz, B., J. D. Wurlod, L. Panzone and T. Swanson, “The Behavioral Effect of Pigovian Regulation: Evidence
From a Field Experiment,” Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 87, January 2018, pp. 190-
205.
41
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
Levinson, A., “Energy Efficiency Standards Are More Regressive Than Energy Taxes: Theory and Evidence,”
Journal of the Association of Environmental and Resource Economists, University of Chicago Press, 6(S1),
2019, pp. 7-36.
Lipsey, R. G. and K. Lancaster, “The General Theory of Second Best,The Review of Economic Studies, 24(1),
January 1956, pp. 11-32.
Mankiw, N. G., "Small Menu Costs and Large Business Cycles: A Macroeconomic Model of Monopoly," The
Quarterly Journal of Economics, 100(2), May 1985, pp. 529538.
Mattauch, L. and C. Hepburn, “Climate Policy When Preferences are Endogenousand Sometimes They
Are,” INET Oxford Working Paper no. 2016-04, July 2016.
Mattauch, C. Hepburn and N. Stern, “Pigou Pushes Preferences: Decarbonisation Options When Preferences
are Endogenous,” CESifo Working Paper 7404, December 2018.
Millar, R., M. Allen, J. Rogelj and P. Friedlingstein, “The Cumulative Carbon Budget and Its Implications,”
Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 32(2), April 2016, pp. 323-342.
Mirrlees, J. A., “An Exploration in the Theory of Optimal Income Taxation,” Review of Economic Studies, 38(2),
April 1971, pp. 175-208.
1975, “Optimal Commodity Taxation in a Two-Class Economy,Journal of Public
Economics, 4(1), February, pp. 27-33.
Narassimhan, E., K. S. Gallagher, S. Koester and J. R. Alejo, “Carbon Pricing in Practice: A Review of Existing
Emissions Trading Systems,” Climate Policy, 18(8), April 2018, pp. 1-25.
Park, J., C. Hepburn and N. Keohane, “Does Benefit Uncertainty Matter for Climate Policy Design? A Case for
Tradable Permit Markets with Banking,” June 25, 2013.
Patrizio, P. S., F. Leduc, S. Kraxner, S. Fuss, G. Kindermann, S. Mesfun, K. Spokas, A. Mendoza, N. MacDowell,
E. Wetterlund, J. Lundgren, E. Dotzauer, P. Yowargana and M. Obersteiner, “Reducing US Coal Emissions Can
Boost Employment,” Joule, 2, November 2018, pp. 116.
Pizer, W. A., “Combining Price and Quantity Controls to Mitigate Global Climate Change,” Journal of Public
Economics, 85(3), September 2002, pp. 409-434.
Roberts, M. J. and M. Spence. “Effluent Charges and Licenses Under Uncertainty,” Journal of Public
Economics, 5(3-4), May 1976, pp. 193-208.
Samuelson, P. A., “A Theory of Induced Innovation Along Kennedy-Weisäcker Lines,” The Review of
Economics and Statistics, 47(4), November 1965, pp. 343-356.
Sandmo, A., “Optimal Taxation in the Presence of Externalities,” The Swedish Journal of Economics, 77(1),
January 1975, pp. 86-98.
Sandel, M. J., What Money Can't Buy: The Moral Limits of Markets, Macmillan, New York, 2012.
Sinclair, P., “High Does Nothing and Rising Is Worse: Carbon Taxes Should Keep Declining to Cut Harmful
Emissions,” The Manchester School, 60(1), March 1992, pp. 41-52.
42
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
1994, “On the Optimum Trend of Fossil Fuel Taxation,” Oxford Economic Papers, 46(1), October, pp.
869-877.
Sterner, T. (Ed.), Fuel Taxes and the Poor: The distributional consequences of gasoline taxation and their
implications for climate policy, RFF Press, Routledge, Washington, D.C., 2012.
Stiglitz, J. E., “The Rate of Discount for Cost-Benefit Analysis and the Theory of the Second Best,”
Discounting for Time and Risk in Energy Policy, R. Lind (Ed.), Resources for the Future, 1982, pp. 151-204.
1986, Economics of the Public Sector, W.W. Norton (2
nd
edition, 1988, 3
rd
edition, 2000), New York.
1987a, “Learning to Learn, Localized Learning and Technological Progress,” Economic Policy and
Technological Performance, P. Dasgupta and Stoneman (eds.), Cambridge University Press, London, pp. 125-
153.
1987b, “Pareto Efficient and Optimal Taxation and the New New Welfare Economics,” in Handbook on
Public Economics, A. Auerbach and M. Feldstein (Eds.), Volume 2, North- Holland, Amsterdam, pp. 991-1042.
1998a, “Pareto Efficient Taxation and Expenditure Policies, With Applications to the Taxation of
Capital, Public Investment, and Externalities,” presented at the Conference in Honor of Agnar Sandmo,
Bergen, January.
1998b, “The Private Uses of Public Interests: Incentives and Institutions,” Journal of Economic
Perspectives, 12(2), Spring, pp. 3-22. (Originally presented as Society of Government Economists
Distinguished Lecture on Economics in Government, ASSA meetings, January 4, 1998.)
2006, “Samuelson and the Factor Bias of Technological Change,” Samuelsonian Economics and the
Twenty
-
First Century, M. Szenberg et al. (Eds.), Oxford University Press, New York, pp. 235-251.
2009, “Simple Formulae for Optimal Income Taxation and the Measurement of Inequality,” in
Arguments for a Better World: Essays in Honor of Amartya Sen, Volume I, Ethics, Welfare, and Measurement,
K. Basu and R. Kanbur (Eds.), Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 535-566. (Revision of IMSSS Technical
Report No. 215, Stanford University, August 1976).
2013, “Sharing the Burden of Saving the Planet: Global Social Justice for Sustainable
Development,” M. Kaldor and J. E. Stiglitz, (Eds.), The Quest for Security: Protection without Protectionism
and the Challenge of Global Governance, Columbia University Press, New York, pp. 161-190.
2014, “Unemployment and Innovation,” NBER Working Paper 20670, November.
2017, “Overcoming the Copenhagen Failure with Flexible Commitments," Global Carbon Pricing: The
Path to Climate Cooperation, P.Cramton, D. J. C. MacKay, A. Ockenfels, and
S. Stoft (Eds.), MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., 2017, pp. 99108; also in Economics of Energy and Environmental
Policy, 4(2), Symposium on International Climate Negotiations, September 2015, pp. 2936.
2018a, ”Unemployment, Welfare, and Innovation,” paper presented to ASSA meetings, Philadelphia,
PA, January.
2018b, “Pareto Efficient Taxation and Expenditures: Pre- and Re-distribution,” Journal of Public
Economics Special Issue in Honor of Sir Tony Atkinson (1944-2017), E. Luttmer and H. Kleven (Eds.), 162, June,
pp. 101119.
43
CREATIVE COMMONS COPYRIGHT 2019 BY THE ROOSEVELT INSTITUTE | ROOSEVELTINSTITUTE.ORG
2018c, “Expert Report in Juliana et al vs the United States of America,” filed June 28.
Stiglitz and B. Greenwald, “Creating a Learning Society: A New Approach to Growth, Development, and Social
Progress,” Columbia University Press, New York, 2014.